The question of what can be the proper subject of ownership — what is property? — is an important theme of libertarianism. It arises in discussion of such diverse topics as slavery, pollution, animal rights and intellectual property. It is with intellectual property (by which is commonly meant, copyright and patent) that the question becomes unusually difficult, for what is being claimed is the ownership of intangibles, of ideas. The title of a recent book, Who Owns What Is In Your Mind?, concretizes a commonsense objection to intellectual property; most people would loudly declare: “no one owns what is in my mind!” Yet, if the information you have is a chemical formula which you accidentally glimpsed, do you have the right to market it as your own over the protests of the chemist who worked a lifetime to perfect it? Do you have the right to publish a book with characters named John Galt and Dagney Taggart? And if not, why not?
Intellectual property was the subject of intensive and unsurpassed debate within the pages of Benjamin Tucker’s libertarian periodical Liberty (1881-1908). Because of this, the best presentation of this question is an overview of the debate. The citations which appear directly after the questions refer to the appropriate issue and page of Liberty.
Intellectual Property and Natural Rights
Although it is usually contended that the intellectual property debate was over the ownership of ideas, this is not quite accurate. James Walker — who wrote under the pseudonym of Tak Kak — was a leading opponent of copyright and patent; he stated: “My thoughts are my property as the air in my lungs is my property …” (March 21, 1891, 4) Both sides of the debate agreed that each man owns his own thoughts which he is free to express or not, as he pleases. Nor did the debate center around an individual’s right to use and dispose of his property, of his own ideas. On this, Walker wrote: “If any person wishes to live by imparting his ideas in exchange for labor, I have nothing to say against his doing so and getting cooperative protection without invading the persons and property of myself and my allies … whatever he can do by contract, cooperation, and boycotting … let him do at his pleasure.” (March 21, 1891, 4)
So long as the monopoly of ideas was contractual, the opponents of intellectual property were content.
The point of contention was the claim that intellectual property was based on natural rights and, therefore, should be protected by law in the same manner that other property, such as land, was protected. Just as you did not require a contract in order to “monopolize” land you had homesteaded, neither did you need a contract to give you just claim to an idea. Both were products of labor and, by natural law principles, the property of their producer. It was the assertion and denial of this claim that formed the backbone of the debate.
The advocates of intellectual property believed that because a man was the first to discover an idea, he was entitled not only to the use of the specific instance of that idea, but also was entitled to prohibit others from similarly using it. Ownership extended from one’s own instance of an idea to all instances of the idea. Spooner (the leading proponent of intellectual property) based this claim of extended ownership on the contention that ideas were the product of labor and that a man justly owns what his labor produces. In The Law of Intellectual Property, Spooner explains: “… the principle of individual property … says that each man has an absolute dominion, as against all other men, over the products and acquisitions of his own labor …” To Walker and Tucker, however, the reward of the labor was the specific idea. More than this could not be claimed because, in the words of Henry George: “No man can justly claim ownership in natural laws, nor in any of the relations which may be perceived by the human mind, nor in any of the potentialities which nature holds for it …” (July 7, 1888, 4) Whether ownership of ideas extended beyond one’s own body was the key question and, because of this, it is more accurate to label the opposing forces as “extensionists” and “anti-extensionists” than as pro and anti intellectual property.
“What is Property?”
Ultimately, the debate over non-contractual copyright and patents revolved around three core issues: What is property? What are the essential characteristics which enable something to be subject to ownership? What is an idea?
[There were also a number of side squabbles which are interesting enough to mention. The anti-extensionists (Tucker, Walker, J. B. Robinson, Wm. Hanson) attacked the Spencerian notion that such ownership, if it did exist, should have a time limit as embodied in the law. The extensionists (Yarros, Simpson, Wm. Lloyd), though greatly influenced by Spencer, agreed that property rights should not expire. There was some debate on utilitarian grounds with extensionists claiming that, without a legal copyright, no one would write great literature. Tucker responded that Shakespeare had penned his works a century prior to the first copyright law. He quoted George Bernard Shaw: “… the cry for copyright is the cry of men who are not satisfied with being paid for their work once, but insist upon being paid twice, thrice, and a dozen times over.” (January 10, 1891, 6)]
“What is property?” remained the central issue. The extensionists maintained that property was simply “wealth that has an owner” which ownership was acquired through discovery or labor. Tucker, however, asked the question in more fundamental terms; he asked why the concept of property existed at all. What was there in the nature of man and of reality that made such a concept necessary? He postulated that property arose as a means of solving conflicts caused by scarcity. Since all goods are scarce, there is competition for their use. Since the same chair cannot be used at the same time and in the same manner by two people, it becomes necessary to determine who should use the chair. Property arose as an answer to this question. “If it were possible,” Tucker wrote, “and if it has always been possible for an unlimited number of individuals to use to an unlimited extent and in an unlimited number of places the same concrete thing at the same time, there would never have been any such thing as the institution of property.”
Ideas, however, could be used at the same time and in the same manner by an infinite number of people. If one man discovers the principle of electricity and builds a generator on his own land, it in no way impedes another man’s ability to discover electricity and build his own generator as well. Extended ownership, therefore, runs counter to the purpose of property, to the problem that the concept was meant to solve.
Furthermore, argued the anti-extensionists, copyright and patents contradict the essential characteristics of property, one of these characteristics being that the property be transferable, that it be alienable. “He who conceives an idea has it in his right,” explained Wm. Hanson. “It is his property; but it is non-transferable. No conceiver of an idea can transfer it bodily from his own brain to that of another, and thus deprive himself of it.” (June 13, 1891, 6) Walker added: “The giver or seller parts with it [property] in conveying it. This characteristic distinguishes property from skill and information.” (May 30, 1891, 3) The anti-extensionists considered transferrability to be a defining characteristic of property.
In response to the question “What is an idea?” the extensionists replied that it was form of wealth and the product of labor. The egoist J. B. Robinson had a different approach. “What is an ‘idea’?” he asked. “Is it made of wood, or iron, or stone? … the idea is nothing objective … that is to say, the idea is not part of the product; it is part of the producer …” (May 16, 1891, 5) Robinson argued that ideas cannot be owned because they are part of a human being. They are the result of labor in the same sense that the muscles on an arm are the result of exercise. It was absurd, however, to say that either the muscle or the idea was a product independent from the producer. As part of the producer, they were not subject to ownership.
Ownership Rights Over an Aspect of Nature
Although copyrights and patents are derivative issues from the question of ownership of ideas in general, most of Liberty‘s debate revolved around them. The debate concerning patents and copyrights began seriously in July, 1888 when Tucker reprinted excerpts from an article by Henry George published in George’s periodical The Standard, “It cannot come from discovery”. (July 7, 1888, 4) This distinction between discovery and production was crucial. The extensionists claimed that when a man discovered the law of electricity and mixed his labor with raw materials to express this natural law in the form of a generator, he had performed the labor of production and, thus, had title to the generator. The anti-extensionists, however, would counter that the act of discovery alone gave the man no more right to the principle of electricity than simply discovering a valley would give him the right to that land. The discoverer, therefore, cannot prevent someone else from discovering — five minutes or five years later — the same principle of nature and from using that principle for his own benefit. To claim otherwise would be to say that the initial discoverer had ownership rights over an aspect of nature, of a physical relationship. Tucker believed that patents violated the libertarian theory of equal liberty. “From the moment a patent or copyright is granted,” he wrote, “no man is free to acquire the same fact — to elaborate from it, if he can, the same new ideas — and in a similar manner employ those new ideas for his private advantage.” (February 7, 1891, 4)
When Victor Yarros offered the Spencerian contention that one would have the right to prove before a jury that one’s instance of the idea was independently discovered, Tucker responded that such a reversal of proof — the defendant would be guilty until proved innocent — ran counter to all all established methods of fair trial. He suggested that Spencer advocated this method because “to go to a jury on a question of independence of invention or authorship, with the burden of proof on the complainant … would be sure victory for the defendant …” (Feb 7, 1891, 4)
Copyrights were handled somewhat differently than patents, which were generally viewed as discoveries of natural law or of physical relationships. The 1888 excerpts from Henry George which sparked the debate were criticized by Tucker due to George’s acceptance of copyright. Tucker stated: “The same argument that demolishes the right of the inventor demolishes the right of the author.” (July 7, 1888, 4) Tucker, however, set the stage for the perceived difference between the two forms of extended ideas when he wrote: “The central injustice of … patent laws is that it compels the race to pay an individual through a long term of years a monopoly price for knowledge that he has discovered today although some other man … in many cases very probably would have discovered it tomorrow.” (Dec 27, 1890, 4)
The Method of Expressing an Idea
The issue that separated patents from copyrights in many people’s minds was probability. Simultaneous inventions are not uncommon and there are many instances of several people “originating” the same theory independently. A commonly cited example is that of Menger, Walras and Jevons, who independently conceived of marginal utility at the same time. Extensionists like Yarros, however, did not think it probable that two men would independently originate Hamlet or A School for Scandal. He claimed that copyright protected not an idea, such as marginal utility, but the particular form of expressing that idea, the actual pattern of words. He wrote: “Copyright would not prevent anyone’s writing a book to express the same ideas that Spencer has expressed; it would simply prevent the appropriation of the fruits of his toil.” (Dec 27, 1890, 4)
Tucker addressed both points. He agreed that it was extremely improbable that two men would write the same poem, but insisted that it was not impossible. Simply throwing letters randomly up in the air, he insisted, would eventually render a piece that began “Shall I compare thee to a summer’s day …” As to the extreme improbability of this, he wrote: “To discuss the degrees of probability … is to shoot wide of the mark. Such questions as this are not to be decided by rule of thumb or by the law of chances, but in accordance with some general principle … among the things not logically impossible, I know of few nearer the limit of possibility than that I should ever decide to publish Liberty in the middle of the desert of Sahara; nevertheless, this would scarcely justify any great political power in giving Stanley a right to stake out a claim comprising that entire region and forbid me to set up a printing press.” (Dec 27, 1890, 4)
As to the ownership of a form of expression, of a pattern of combining words, Tucker commented: “… the particular combination of words belongs to neither of us … the method of expressing an idea is itself an idea, and therefore not appropriable.” (July 7, 1888, 4) Walker added: “If the printer may not copy new books, of course, the shoemaker may not copy new shoes …” (March 21, 1891, 5) Here, Walker pointed out that all ideas (whether of shoes, poems, chairs, hairstyles, or clothing) have distinctive forms of expression, but only in the case of literary expression does the question of granting a legal monopoly arise. The consistent extensionist would have to admit that since speech is a product of labor and a form of expression, everyone should be entitled to legal protection for every sentence they spoke to that no one thereafter could speak that sentence without consent. Spooner does, in fact, come very close to this position.
The Debate Has Not Been Resolved
Another argument used by the anti-extensionists was that to publish and sell a work without a contract to protect its contents was, in effect, to abandon it. This was counter to Spooner’s contention that the law must presume a man wishes to retain control over his property so long as it has any value to him. Thus, if an idea is valuable, to publish it does not decrease its value, and it remains legally protected property. Needless to say, Tucker analyzed it differently. He wrote: “If a man scatters money in the street, he does not therefore formally relinquish title to it … but those who pick it up are thereafter considered the rightful owners … Similarly a man who reproduces his writings by thousands and spreads them everywhere voluntarily abandons his right of privacy and those who read them … no more put themselves by the act under any obligations in regard to the author than those who pick up scattered money put themselves under obligations to the scatterer.” (April 18, 1891, 5)
Tucker expressed the core of this argument and of his position on intellectual property when he exclaimed: “You want your invention to yourself? Then keep it to yourself.” (Feb 21, 1891, 5)
That copyright and patent are useful social devices to achieve desirable ends was never questioned. It was the basis of copyright and patent that was questioned. The extensionists argued that they could be justly enforced only through contract. Perhaps the most important aspect of the debate was its emphasis upon the question so fundamental to libertarianism — what is property?
This debate has not been resolved in libertarianism. To the extent that such ‘gray’ areas are discussed and dissected, we will come closer and closer to fully defining what is ‘property’, what is ‘right’. In doing so, we will once again be standing on the shoulders of giants.
From an interchange on Google+ about this with Craig Hayne: my reply:
“1) Contracts would not be valid. A contract is an exchange of property and/or labor.”
This is not right. You need to read up on the Rothbardian title transfer theory of contract. See my article here: http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/17_2/17_2_2.pdf. In short: a contract is a transfer (not necessarily exchange) of title to an owned resource (not labor). For it to be “valid” the owner merely needs to be the owner of the resource and manifest his consent to transfer the title–either now, or later; either conditionally, or unconditionally. Thus, I can say “I hereby give you $1000 next Tuesday IF you paint my fence.” That is a unilateral, conditional transfer of title to money, based on a condition being fulfilled. So if you do paint the fence, then this triggers the trasnfer of money to you. It does NOT mean you owned or sold your labor. Only that you used your ownership of your body to perform an action that resulted in your obtaining title to someone’s money.
” So without the ownership of labor, you’re not morally obligated to pay a contractor who came to work on your home — he doesn’t own his labor.”
Contracts are not about moral obligations. See Rothbad (discussed in my article). Labor is NOT owned.
“2) People are not responsible for their actions. If people don’t own the products of their actions, then they cannot be held morally responsible when their actions harm others. ”
This is just confused and false. It is not because you “own” your actions, or the “products of” your actions, that you are responsible for them. It is precisely because there are only property rights in scarce resources, and therefore, you have no right to use resources owned by others. That is, you have no right to engage in actions that use or control or invade or alter the physical integrity of others’ owned resources, without their consent. If you do, you have committed trespass, aggression. That is what gives rise to responsbility/liability. It has nothing whatsoever to do with an overly metaphorical, nonrigorous, liberal arts type poetic vague loosey goosey idea that we “own” our “actions”.
“People are responsible for their actions, both good and bad.”
How can you be responsible for a good action? What does this even mean? If it’s good presumably no one’s rights are violated, so you have nothign to be liable for.
” If they harm others, they should be held accountable,”
Yes, this follows directly from the libertarian/Lockean view of property rights in scarce resources–i.e., the non-aggression principle.
” and if they create something of value, then the product of that creation should be considered property. ”
This “then” does not follow at all. It is purely an assertion, a muddle, based on confusion about core property and libertarian concepts. It is the result of sloppy thinking, overuse of metaphors and vague terms, and equivocation. It’s also a non sequitur.
“Property is both the object of, and the product of action, which is labor.”
Let’s be clear here. Property is not an object, technically speaking, though we sometimes use th word this way. Property is a relation between an agent/actor, and a scarce resource. So you have a property in an apple, you have a property in your body. Sometimes the apple and body are called your property, in another sense of the word.
The object of action is NOT scarce resources (or “property” in the latter sense). It is simply the removal of felt uneasiness; some desired end state or situation. For example I may desire to hear an aria. So I find a way to make this happen. The end is not an object; it is a change in what would have occurred absent my acting. My acting necessarily employs means–that is, scarce resources. So that is why we need property rights in scarce resources: SO THAT they may be employed peacefully and without conflict, to achieve desired ends. So the object of action is the end, whatever that may be; and action employs scarce resources to achieve those ends.
The object of action is NOT “labor.” Rather, labor is just another word for action, or an aspect of action, such as effort or work. If my goal is to have a nice crop of corn, I have to interact causally with the world in employing scarce means–seeds, plow, dirt, land, water, fertilizer, rake, shovel, storage shed, and so on–to achieve my end. This is what action (or “labor”) is: using your body to interact wtih the scarce resources so as to take advantage of their causal relation with other things in the world, so that you cause things to change from what would otherwise occur (e.g., there would be no corn).
The role of knowledge or information, or mental thinking and creativity, is to guide your action. To help you understand the causal laws, to help you select the right means so that your end state is achieved–that is, so that your action is successful; that is, so that you achieve a profit. You do not own the information; you have knowledge in your brain, but it is not a means of action, it is not a scarce resource. It is not a means you employ to achieve an end. It is what allows you to be an actor–to have intelligence and to make choices about appropriate means, based on your understanding (knowledge) of causal laws. The knowledge guides your choices and actions. The action employs scarce means to achieve ends. The object of action is the end sought, not the means used to achieve that object/end.
“Liberty without property is action without the product of the action, and is futility itself.”
This is more metaphorical nonsense. This is not the way to go about thinking clearly about libertarian ideas.
“We do not develop property as a utilitarian application to solve scarcity;”
Wrong. If there were no scarcity there would be no conflict and no need to allocate, to ration, to economize. Property would be nonsensical and purposeless.
” rather we develop property as the product of liberty because we need to be able to take action in order to live.”
You only need to take action to live, because we live in a world of scarcity. Whether you are Crusoe or in society, you need to act: to employ means (scarce resources) to achieve ends. The (large) subset of humans who (for whatever reason) prefer to have a cooperative, peaceful, productive society in which people are able to use resources productively in action, without having to battle violently all the time with others over these resources–people whom I call “civilized”–these people naturally, as a consequence of their basic “civilized” values, will also value the institution of property: the allocation of ownership or titles to resources, to specified owners, so that resources may be used peacefullly and productively.
“Liberty is freedom of action, and property is the product of that action.”
This is confused Galambosianism. Even if by “property” you are referring to scarce resources, they become property by being appropriated from an unowned state in the state of nature–by being homesteaded. OR by being acquired from a previous owner (contract). That is it. They are NOT “produced.” Production simply means: you transform or rearrange a given resource into a different, more valuable arrangement. But to do this you already have to own the resource that you transform. When you transform it–“production”–you create wealth because you make your existing owned thing more valuable or useful, but you do not create any new property rights or property titles. The idea that creation or production is a source of property rights is a confusion. It is not. Only homesteading creates a property right, and the only way to acquire title to some thing is either by homesteading it, or by contratually acquiring it from some previous owner/homesteader.
You must log in to post a comment. Log in now.